Michael Tam
Dr Michael Tam is a clinical academic Specialist General Practitioner, combining the provision of family medicine, research, health services development, and governance. Michael’s clinical interest is in the whole-person primary care of people living with mental illness. He is actively involved in mental health policy, strategy, and governance, with local, state, and national bodies. Michael’s research is in integrated care and preventive care in general practice. He has expertise in both qualitative and quantitative research methods.
Tags
alcohol
alcohol user disorder
antibiotics
Australian Journal of General Practice
beliefs and attitudes
brief interventions
CAM
cardiovascular disease
Chinese women
common cold
contraception
COVID-19
e-learning
EBM
emergency departments
ethics
general practice
general practitioners
infection control
integrated care
learning and teaching
medical certificates
medical education
medical myths
mental health
newsGP
older people
older person
p-values
paediatrics
pain
patients
preventive health
primary care
public health
research
research ethics
risky drinking
screening
shared-decision making
statin
statistics
vitamin C
vocational training
warts
Recent Posts
- Integrated Care for People Living With Rare Disease: A Scoping Review on Primary Care Models in Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development Countries
- Development and pilot testing of the Population And ContExt adaption of decision aids (PACE) framework
- Heavy drinkers’ expectations and experiences when discussing alcohol use during a general practice visit in Australia: A qualitative study
- RACGP Future Leaders Program 2023 Breakfast Oration
- Multifaceted intervention to increase the delivery of alcohol brief interventions in primary care: a mixed-methods process analysis
- General practitioners’ perspectives regarding early developmental surveillance for autism within the australian primary healthcare setting: a qualitative study
- Parental experience of an early developmental surveillance programme for autism within Australian general practice: a qualitative study
- Supporting conversations about medicines and deprescribing: GPs’ perspectives on a Medicines Conversation Guide
- Melanoma risk assessment and management: a qualitative study among Australian GPs
- Watch me grow integrated (WMG-I): protocol for a cluster randomised controlled trial of a web-based surveillance approach for developmental screening in primary care settings
Categories
- Australian Doctor (4)
- Conference presentation (41)
- eBook (3)
- General article (85)
- GP careers presentation (1)
- GPSN presentation (2)
- Interview (39)
- Journal article (39)
- Lecture/Tutorial (12)
- Letter/Comment (13)
- Medical Observer (47)
- Public presentation (4)
- Research presentation (25)
- The Medical Republic (1)
- Tweet (5)
- Type (230)
- Audio (3)
- Book (6)
- PDF (124)
- Powerpoint (7)
- Prezi (20)
- Radio (10)
- Video (21)
- Web article (113)
- Website (4)
- Workshop (1)
Mar 21 2012
Comment: Response to “Tarring complementary medicine is anti-choice”
The following is a comment to an opinion piece, “Tarring complementary medicine is anti-choice” written by Kerryn Phelps in Medical Observer. My comments were published online on 21 March 2012.
I concur with some of the statements in the comments and feel I must support my colleagues who are members of the Friends of Science in Medicine (FSM).
The categorisation of health interventions by cultural tradition, e.g., “complimentary” or “Western”, is perhaps unhelpful. A better way to group interventions is by considering efficacy, evidence, and plausibility.
Firstly, there are interventions that have both good empiric evidence for efficacy, and high scientific plausibility (e.g., aspirin for secondary prevention of cardiovascular disease). These can be considered to be the “best” interventions, insofar our confidence that they work.
In the second group, there are interventions that have good empiric evidence for efficacy, have some scientific plausibility, but the mechanism of action is not clearly known (e.g., atypical antipsychotics for bipolar I disorder). Many modern medications fall into this category. A priority of research policy should be in investigating these interventions.
A third group are interventions that have poor (or a lack of) empiric evidence for efficacy, but are highly plausible (e.g., using new oral hypoglycaemic agents to prevent macrovascular outcomes in individuals with diabetes). Again, a priority of research should be in collecting empiric evidence – we can be misled by thinking that plausible therapies will have clinically meaningful effects.
A fourth group are interventions that have poor, inconsistent, or a lack of empiric evidence for efficacy and also lack scientific plausibility (e.g., acupuncture for most conditions). It can be argued that research should take place if the treatment is popular (potential public health impact) or there are case reports of efficacy (to assess more rigorously). However, it is unclear that these sorts of therapies should be routinely RECOMMENDED.
A fifth group are interventions that have good empiric evidence for lack of efficacy, and are implausible (e.g., homoeopathy for most conditions, or antibiotics for treatment of the common cold). These intervention strategies should be abandoned.
I’ll leave it to the reader to reflect on where interventions that are typically considered “Western” or “CAM” fall into that scheme.
The problem with focussing on the labels of “CAM” or “Western” medicine is that it is easy to make fallacious arguments. Yes, not all therapies in “Western” medicine are well based in evidence – but that does not imply that empiric evidence of efficacy and scientific plausibility are not of key importance. Similarly, not all “CAM” therapies lack evidence and scientific plausibility – but that does not imply that the majority of such therapies have either.
Individual interventions need to be judged on their own merits, and the framework for assessment should be on evidence-based scientific principles. Science is not a brand – it is simply an approach with specific methods and tools that allows us to appraise and understand the empiric universe.
Phelps’ points about Vioxx, Reductil, etc., misses the true lessons from those events. These medical scandals highlight the necessity of evidence-based and scientific medicine. When individuals and health companies sell and promote health interventions, they are incentivised to exaggerate the true utility of these treatments. I agree entirely that those scandals represent failures within Medicine. Nevertheless, we should reflect that exposition of poor interventions can occur, even if late. Where is the “scandal” in the chiropractic world that vertebral subluxations do not exist? We need more science in healthcare, not less!
Phelps is correct that “choice” may be restricted. Healthcare recommendations given by medical practitioners SHOULD be restricted by biomedical ethics. Fundamentally, our suggested therapies must be guided by an empirical understanding of reality. Individual patients are free to have any and all health beliefs and this is respected by a patient-centred model of practice. However, ethical practitioners should not engage in a conspiracy of magical thinking with their patients. It is an audacious misrepresentation to suggest that members of the FSM support paternalistic doctor-patient relationships.
Share this:
Like this: